Thursday, October 7, 2021

Dissertation biographical sketch

Dissertation biographical sketch

dissertation biographical sketch

(SAMPLE BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH) 5. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. John Smith was born in Houston, Texas. After completing his schoolwork at Lamar High School in Houston in , John entered Southwest Texas State University in San Marcos, Texas. During the summers of and , he attended the University of Colorado. He received a Feb 25,  · Attach Biographical Sketch. Provide a biographical sketch for each PD/PI. Applicants for dissertation research awards (e.g., R36) should, in addition to addressing the points noted above, also include a description of their career goals, their intended career trajectory, and their interest in the specific areas of research designated in the NSF's mission is to advance the progress of science, a mission accomplished by funding proposals for research and education made by scientists, engineers, and educators from across the country



My Bibliography - My NCBI Help - NCBI Bookshelf



Kurt Friedrich Gödel b. He is widely known for his Incompleteness Theorems, which are among the handful of landmark theorems in twentieth century mathematics, but his work touched every field of mathematical logic, if it was not in most cases their original stimulus. In his philosophical work Gödel formulated and defended mathematical Platonism, the view that mathematics is a descriptive science, or alternatively the view that the concept of mathematical truth is objective.


On the basis of that viewpoint he laid the foundation for the program of conceptual analysis within set theory see below. Kurt Gödel was born on Dissertation biographical sketch 28, in what was then the Austro-Hungarian city of Brünn, and what is now Brno in the Czech Republic. Health problems notwithstanding, Gödel proved to be an exemplary student at primary school and later the Gymnasium, excelling especially in mathematics, languages and religion.


Upon his graduation from the Gymnasium in Brno in Gödel enrolled in the University of Vienna, dissertation biographical sketch, attending dissertation biographical sketch on physics, his initial field of interest, lectures on philosophy given by Heinrich Gomperz, and lectures on mathematics.


Gödel learned his logic from Rudolph Carnap and from Hans Hahn, eventually graduating under Hahn with a Dr. in mathematics in The main theorem of his dissertation was the completeness theorem for first order logic Gödel Though Gödel was not himself a logical positivist, those discussions were a crucial formative influence.


The s were a prodigious decade for Gödel. After publishing his dissertation inhe published his groundbreaking incompleteness theorems inon the basis of which he was granted his Habilitation in and a Privatdozentur at the University of Vienna in Other publications of the s include those on the decision problem for the predicate calculus, on the length of proofs, dissertation biographical sketch, and on differential and projective geometry.


See Sigmund Finally, Gödel was found fit for military service by the Nazi government in All of these events were decisive in influencing his decision to leave Austria indissertation biographical sketch, when he and his wife Adele emigrated to the United States. Upon arrival Gödel took up an appointment as an ordinary member at the Institute for Advanced Study; he would become a permanent member of the Institute in and would be granted his professorship in Gödel and his wife were granted American citizenship in April He would remain dissertation biographical sketch the Institute until his retirement in The Gödels never returned to Europe.


For the revision of it fromdissertation biographical sketch, see Gödel Gödel died in Princeton on January 14, at the age of For further biographical material, see GödelKleenedissertation biographical sketch, KreiselTaussky-Todd and Yourgrau These will be treated in the sequel to this dissertation biographical sketch. The completeness question for the first order predicate calculus was stated precisely and in print for the first time in by Hilbert and Ackermann in their text Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik Hilbert and Ackermanna text with which Gödel would have been quite familiar.


An essential difference with earlier efforts discussed below and elsewhere, dissertation biographical sketch, dissertation biographical sketch. in Zach dissertation biographical sketch, is that Gödel defines meticulously all the relevant basic concepts.


The Completeness Theorem is stated as follows:. An expression is in dissertation biographical sketch form if all the quantifiers occur at the beginning. The degree of an expression or formula is the number of alternating blocks of quantifiers at the beginning of the formula, dissertation biographical sketch, assumed to begin with universal quantifiers.


Thus the question of completeness reduces to formulas of degree dissertation biographical sketch. Gödel defines a book-keeping device, a well-ordering of all tuples of variables arising from a need to satisfy φ as dictated by Q.


Or more precisely, finite conjunctions of these in increasing length. See below. This lemma is the main step missing from the various earlier attempts at the proof due to Löwenheim and Skolem, and, in the context of the completeness theorem for first order logic, renders the connection between syntax and semantics completely explicit.


We show that this is either refutable or satisfiable. We make the following definitions:. Case 1: For some dissertation biographical sketchφ n is not satisfiable. Case 2: Each φ n is satisfiable. In this way we obtain a tree which is finitely branching but infinite. The union of the models on B forms a model M with universe { x 0x 1 ,…}.


Since M satisfies each φ nthe original formula φ holds in M, dissertation biographical sketch. So φ is satisfiable and we are done, dissertation biographical sketch. Thus this proof of the Completeness Theorem gives also the Löweheim-Skolem Theorem see below. Gödel extends the result to countably many formulas and to the case of first order logic with identity.


He also proves the independence of the axioms. In Gödel published the paper based on his thesis Gödel notable also for the inclusion of the compactness theorem, which is only implicitly stated in the thesis.


The theorem as stated by Gödel in Gödel is as follows: a countably infinite set of quantificational formulas is satisfiable if and only if every finite subset of those formulas is satisfiable. Gödel uses compactness to derive a generalization of the completeness theorem.


The Compactness Theorem would become one of the main tools in the then fledgling subject of model theory. A theory is said to be categorical if it has only one model up to isomorphism; it is λ-categorical if it has only one model of cardinality λ, up to isomorphism.


One of the main consequences of the completeness theorem is that categoricity fails for Peano arithmetic and for Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. In detail, regarding the first order Peano axioms henceforth PAthe existence of non-standard models of them actually follows from completeness together with compactness, dissertation biographical sketch.


One constructs these models, which contain infinitely large integers, as follows: add a new constant symbol c to the language of arithmetic.


This simple fact about models of Peano arithmetic was not pointed out by Gödel in any of the publications connected with the Completeness Theorem from that time, and it seems not to have been noticed by the general logic community until much later.


But Skolem never mentions the fact that the existence of such models follows from the completeness and compactness theorems. As for set theory, the failure dissertation biographical sketch categoricity was already taken note of by Skolem inbecause it follows from the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem which Skolem arrived at that year; see Skolembased on Löwenheim and Skolem : any first order theory in a countable language that has a model has a countable model.


But in recent times I have seen to my surprise that so many mathematicians think that these axioms of set theory provide the ideal foundation for mathematics; therefore it seemed to me that the time had come to publish a critique. English translation taken from van Heijenoortp.


In a letter to Hao Wang, Gödel takes note of the fact that his completeness proof had almost been obtained by Skolem in In fact, giving a finitary proof of the consistency of analysis was a key desideratum of what was then known as the Hilbert program, along with proving its completeness, dissertation biographical sketch. For a discussion of the Hilbert Program the reader is referred to the standard references: Sieg, ; MancosuZachTait and Tait The First Incompleteness Theorem provides a counterexample to completeness by exhibiting an arithmetic statement which is neither provable nor refutable in Peano arithmetic, though true in the standard model.


The Second Incompleteness Theorem dissertation biographical sketch that the consistency of arithmetic cannot be proved in arithmetic itself. As an aside, von Neumann understood the two theorems this way, even before Gödel did. In fact von Neumann went much further in taking the view that they showed the infeasibility of classical mathematics altogether. As he wrote to Carnap in June of It would take Gödel himself a few years to see that those aspects of the Hilbert Program had been decisively refuted by his results Mancosu We see that Gödel first tried to reduce the consistency problem for analysis to that of arithmetic.


Gödel then noticed that such paradoxes would not necessarily arise if truth were replaced by provability. But this means that arithmetic truth and arithmetic provability are not co-extensive — whence the First Incompleteness Theorem. See Gödel a and Gödel b respectively. From those accounts we see that the undefinability of truth in arithmetic, a result credited to Tarski, was likely obtained in some form by Gödel by Gödel himself used a system related to that defined in Principia Mathematica, but containing Peano arithmetic.


Naturally this implies consistency and follows from the assumption that the natural numbers dissertation biographical sketch the axioms of Peano arithmetic. One of the main technical tools used in the proof is Gödel numberinga mechanism which assigns natural numbers to terms and formulas of our formal theory P.


There are different ways of doing this. The most common is based on the unique representation of natural numbers as products of powers of primes. Each symbol s of number theory is assigned a positive natural number s in a fixed but arbitrary way, e. In this way we can assign Gödel numbers to formulas, sequences of formulas once a method for distinguishing when one formula ends and another begins has been adoptedand most notably, proofs. Another concept required to carry out the formalization is the dissertation biographical sketch of numeralwise expressibility of number theoretic predicates.


A number-theoretic formula φ n 1…, n k is numeralwise expressible in P if for each tuple of natural numbers n 1…, n k :. where n is the formal term which denotes the natural number n. In Pthis dissertation biographical sketch S S … S 0 …where n is the number of iterations of the successor function applied to the constant symbol 0. One of the principal goals is to numeralwise express the predicate.


Reaching this goal involves defining forty-five relations, each defined in terms of the preceding ones, dissertation biographical sketch. These dissertation biographical sketch are all primitive recursive. The forty-fifth primitive recursive relation defined is Prf xyand the forty-sixth is. which without being primitive recursive, is however obtained from Prf xy by existentially quantifying x. In Theorem V of his paper, Gödel proves that any number theoretic predicate which is primitive recursive is numeralwise expressible in P.


Thus since Prf xy and substitution are primitive recursive, these are decided by P when closed terms are substituted for the free variables x and y. This is the heart of the matter as we will see. On the contrary Prov Sb r u 1 … u n Z x 1 … Z x nis a meaningless string of logical and arithmetical symbols. Although Gödel constructs a fixed point in the course of proving the incompleteness theorem, he does not state the fixed point theorem explicitly.


The fixed point theorem is as follows:. A sentence is refutable from a theory if its negation is provable. The First Incompleteness Theorem as Gödel stated it is as follows:. Proof: By judicious coding of syntax referred to above, write a formula Prf xy [ 11 ] of number theory, representable in Pso that.




G7: Writing a Biographical Sketch

, time: 6:11





Bentley Academic Technology Center | Bentley University


dissertation biographical sketch

Svante Arrhenius Biographical S vante August Arrhenius was born on February 19, , the son of Svante Gustaf Arrhenius and Carolina Christina Thunberg. His ancestors were farmers; his uncle became Professor of Botany and Rector of the Agricultural High School at Ultuna near Uppsala and later Secretary of The Swedish Academy of Agriculture Feb 13,  · Biographical Sketch Kurt Gödel was born on April 28, in what was then the Austro-Hungarian city of Brünn, and what is now Brno in the Czech Republic. Gödel’s father Rudolf August was a businessman, and his mother Marianne was a well-educated and cultured woman to whom Gödel remained close throughout his life, as witnessed by the long Biographical I was born in Milwaukee, Wisconsin, on June 15, My father, an electrical engineer, had come to the United States in after earning his engineering diploma at the Technische Hochschule of Darmstadt, Germany. He was an inventor and designer of electrical control gear, later also a patent attorney

No comments:

Post a Comment